The “repugnant conclusion” that an Oxford philosopher couldn’t escape
If human happiness is an absolute good, would 1 billion slightly happy people be better than 1 million incredibly happy people?
Thanos did not study under Derek Parfit. In part, this is because Thanos was a Titanian Eternal warlord, an alien born on a moon of Saturn. Parfit, however, was a British moral philosopher who taught at the University of Oxford starting in the 1970s. But I also know this because Thanos and Parfit came to very different philosophical conclusions.
Thanos’ logic in the Marvel movies — spoiler alert for Marvel movies before 2020 — was that, “If life is left unchecked, life will cease to exist…It needs correction.” Given that the Universe’s resources are finite and life seems to show no signs of limiting itself, he thought we needed to step in and increase the quality of life. Thanos argued that it would be better to have fewer people enjoying more, rather than lots of people “enjoying” barely anything.
In this week’s Mini Philosophy interview, I spoke with David Edmonds. Edmonds co-created one of the world’s most popular philosophy podcasts, Philosophy Bites, and he has also recently written a book on Parfit, who came to the opposite conclusion from Thanos. But he wasn’t happy about it — his “repugnant conclusion” bothered him right until the end of his career.
So, what is the repugnant conclusion, and why was it such an intractable thorn in the side of one of the greatest modern philosophers?
The repugnant conclusion
The repugnant conclusion is a kind of self-induced reductio ad absurdum where Parfit was forced to accept its arguments on the basis of certain first principles. His first principle in this case was the belief that a good action is one that creates the most happiness. A good world is one with the most overall happiness. This is a basic utilitarian principle, and while it somewhat avoids the issue of “What does happiness mean?” I suspect most people operate a version of this principle in their everyday dealings with other people.
The problem, though, is a mathematical one. This is how Edmonds describes it:
“Imagine a world a bit like our world with, let’s say, eight billion people in it. And let’s say everybody has a good life. There’s nobody in severe destitution. We all have nice lives. We spend our time reading philosophy books and playing golf. Whatever. And we’re all very happy.”
“Now, imagine a world billions and billions of times bigger than that, where there are trillions of people whose lives are only just better than nothing. Which is better: the former world where we’re all playing golf and enjoying ourselves, or the latter world where there are trillions of people whose happiness levels are kind of only just above zero on the ledger?”
Parfit argues that we must conclude the latter world is “better” because it has more overall happiness for more people.
An unavoidable endpoint
Parfit never came to peace with the repugnant conclusion, but he couldn’t find a way to avoid it. What were the options? We could deny that more people make the world better — but that leads to the counterintuitive view that creating happy lives has no value at all. A (just about) happy person is a good thing, so why not a trillion (just about) happy people? Another option is to argue for an upper limit to population value — a kind of diminishing return on human happiness. But that quickly runs into arbitrariness: Why would adding a happy person be good up to one number, and then suddenly not?
Edmonds’ answer is to examine the happiness calculus more closely. Under traditional utilitarianism, “happiness” is defined as having more pleasure than suffering. Edmonds thinks there are two problems with this.
First, Edmonds argues that “there is an asymmetry between happiness and suffering. You can’t put pain on one side and happiness on the other. Philosophers make a mistake in thinking that there’s suffering over there and happiness on the other side, and I don’t think that’s the way we should think about it.”
Second is that unavoidable issue: Who defines happiness, and by what metric? “It’s interesting that when we’re happy, we’re not aware that we’re happy. It’s when we’re doing something else, and it’s only in retrospect that you look back and say, ‘Yeah, I was in the flow.’ Happiness is a kind of flow.”
If it’s often difficult for us to measure our own happiness in a timely and meaningful way, good luck trying to measure happiness on a universal scale.
The very real future
As with all good philosophical thought experiments, the repugnant conclusion has real-life implications. It’s something we grapple with as a society, but also in policy and the courts.
For example, when it comes to climate change, the question becomes whether we should prioritize policies that benefit future generations, even if those lives are marginal or precarious. Within the idea of “AI long-termism,” groups like OpenAI and the effective altruists argue that we must preserve civilization itself — not for us, but for the vast numbers of people who might one day exist. And when we consider global development policy, should we direct resources toward lifting current lives out of poverty, or toward ensuring a larger, stable population can exist in the long run?
Parfit’s thought experiment lingers behind these questions. It’s about the quality of a life set against quantity. It’s about the value of those alive today against those who might be alive in the future. As with all ethical questions, there are no easy answers, but we might be forced to find and live by an answer, nonetheless.
Jonny is the creator of the Mini Philosophy social network. He’s an internationally bestselling author of three books and the resident philosopher at Big Think. He's known all over the world for making philosophy accessible, relatable, and fun.
More Big Think content:
Big Think | Big Think Business | Starts with a Bang | Big Think Books
This is nonsense. (The philosophy, not your writing about it. 😅)
More people reduces happiness beyond a certain point, it does not increase it. And I reject the conclusion that “happiness = good.” Happiness is ephemeral and subjective. We could make the whole world “happy” by dumping narcotics into everyone’s water supply, but that would not, I think most of us would agree, be a “good” thing.
The questions beg many questions, which strongly suggests that they are at least largely invalid.
For one thing, the essay begs such questions as that happiness is additive, possibly even quantifiable.
And that unhappiness is like that too.
And that unhappiness is in some sense the negative of happiness, so that if we have a million units of happiness (beatits), we have a million times as much as if we had just one unit, minus the number of units of misery (miserits) coexisting in the population .
And that if we had one person a million times happier (call it one mega-beatit) than a million others with net zero beatits, that would be just as desirable as having a million with just a weeny single beatit each.
And that if we had a population sharing two mega-beatits, plus one mega-miserit, that would be the same as a population sharing one mega-beatits.
Maybe that makes sense to someone, but as a thought experiment, it leaves me with a rapidly rising miserit titre.